Outline of algebraic structures

In universal algebra, a branch of pure mathematics, an algebraic structure is a variety or quasivariety. Abstract algebra is primarily the study of algebraic structures and their properties. Some axiomatic formal systems that are neither varieties nor quasivarieties, called nonvarieties below, are included among the algebraic structures by tradition.

Other web lists of algebraic structures, organized more or less alphabetically, include Jipsen and PlanetMath. These lists mention many structures not included below, and may present more information about some structures than is presented here.

Contents

Generalities

An algebraic structure consists of one or two sets closed under some operations, functions, and relations, satisfying a number of axioms, including none. This definition of an algebraic structure should not be taken as restrictive. Anything that satisfies the axioms defining a structure is an instance of that structure, regardless of how many other axioms that instance happens to satisfy. For example, all groups are also semigroups and magmas.

Structures are listed below in approximate order of increasing complexity as follows:

If structure B is under structure A and more indented, then A is interpretable in B, meaning that all theorems of A are theorems of B. The converse is usually not the case.

A structure is trivial if the cardinality of S is less than 2, and is otherwise nontrivial.

Varieties

Identities are equations formulated using only the operations the structure allows, and variables that are tacitly universally quantified over a set that is part of the definition of the structure. Hence identities contain no sentential connectives, existentially quantified variables, or relations of any kind other than equality and the operations the structure allows.

If the axioms defining an algebraic structure are all identities--or can be recast as identities--the structure is a variety (not to be confused with algebraic variety in the sense of algebraic geometry). Nonidentities can often be recast as identities. For example, any lattice inequality of the form α≤β can always be recast as the identity α∧β=α.

An important result is that given any variety C and any underlying set X, the free object F(X)∈C exists.

Simple structures

No binary operation.

Group-like structures

Group-like structures
Totality Associativity Identity Inverses
Group Yes Yes Yes Yes
Monoid Yes Yes Yes No
Semigroup Yes Yes No No
Loop Yes No Yes Yes
Quasigroup Yes No No No
Magma Yes No No No
Groupoid No Yes Yes Yes
Category No Yes Yes No
Semicategory No Yes No No

See magma for a list of the many properties that a group-like structures may possess. The diagram to the right summarizes the defining properties of:

All group-like structures feature a primary (and often unique) binary or ternary operation, which usually (e.g., for semigroups and hoops) associates. This operation will nearly always be denoted here by concatenation, and when it is binary, will be called "group product." If group product associates, brackets are not required to resolve the order of operation. When group product does not associate (e.g., quasigroups, semiheaps, loops, implication algebras), an embedded period indicates the grouping. Examples: xy.z, x.yz.

For Steiner magmas, abelian groups, logic algebras, bands, equivalence algebras, and hoops, group product also commutes. Commutativity may be added to any group-like structure for which it is not already the case.

Groups, logic algebras, lattices, and loops feature a unary operation, denoted here by enclosure in parentheses.

For monoids, loops, and sloops, S is a pointed set.

One binary operation.

The following two structures form a bridge connecting magmas and lattices:
  • Lattice: a semilattice with a unary operation, dualization, denoted (x) and satisfying the absorption law, x(xy) = (x(xy)) = x. xx = x is now provable.

Two binary operations.

Three binary operations. In addition to group product, quasigroups feature 2 binary operations denoted by infix "/" and "\". These added operations permit axiomatizing the defining property of quasigroups, cancellation, by means of identities alone.

The following diagram summarizes two possible paths from magma to group.

NOTE:

One ternary operation, heap product, denoted xyz:

Lattice-like structures

The binary operations meet and join, which characterize nearly all structures in this section, are idempotent, by assumption or proof. Latticoids are the only lattice-like structure that do not associate. N.B. "Lattice" is also employed in a number of group-theoretic contexts, including to refer to a discrete subgroup of the real vector space Rn that spans Rn.

Some concepts from order theory that recur in lattice theory:

One binary operation, one of meet or join, and denoted by concatenation. The two structures below are also magmas; see the preceding section.

Two binary operations, meet (infix ∧) and join (infix ∨). Duality means that interchanging all meets and joins preserves truth.

Three structures whose intended interpretations are first order logic:
Converse is an involution and distributes over composition so that (AB)\breve{\ } = B\breve{\ }A\breve{\ }. Converse and composition each distribute over join.[8]

Three binary operations:

  • Boolean semigroup: a Boolean algebra with an added binary operation that associates, distributes over join, and is annihilated by 0.
  • Implicative lattice: a distributive lattice with a third binary operation, implication, that distributes left and right over each of meet and join.
  • Brouwerian algebra: a distributive lattice with a greatest element and a third binary operation, denoted by infix " ' ", satisfying ((xy)≤z)∧(yx)' z.

Four or more binary operations:

The following Hasse diagram illustrates some pathways from a very general concept, partially ordered sets, to the oldest and most researched lattice, Boolean algebra. This diagram reveals some of the hierarchical structure linking a number of important types of lattices, not all discussed above because some are not varieties. This diagram consists of a number of links of the form AB, each meaning that structure A is included in structure B.

Lattice ordered structures

S includes distinguished elements and is closed under additional operations, so that the axioms for a semigroup, monoid, group, or a ring are satisfied.

Ring-like structures

Two binary operations, addition and multiplication. That multiplication has a 0 is either an axiom or a theorem.

N.B. The above definitions of rng, ring, and semiring do not command universal assent:

Modules and algebras

These structures feature a set R whose elements are scalars, denoted by Greek letters, and a set S whose members are denoted by Latin letters. For every ring R, there is a corresponding variety of R-modules.

Quasivarieties

A quasivariety is a variety with one or more axioms that are quasiidentities. Let Greek letters be metavariables denoting identities. A quasiidentity then takes the form (α1∧,...,∧αn) → β.

Magmas

A magma (sometimes called "groupoid", or "algebra of type (2)") is a set equipped with a binary operation.

Cancellative

Combinatory logic

The elements of S are higher order functions, and concatenation denotes the binary operation of function composition.

Graphs

One set, V a finite set of vertices, and a binary relation EV2, adjacency, consisting of edges. No operations.

Lattices

Ring-like

Universal classes

Partial order for nonlattices

If the partial order relation ≤ is added to a structure other than a lattice, the result is a partially ordered structure. These are discussed in Birkhoff (1967: chpts. 13-15, 17) using a differing terminology. Examples include:

Nonvarieties

Nonvarieties cannot be axiomatized solely with identities and quasiidentities. Many nonidentities are of three very simple kinds:

  1. The requirement that S (or R or K) be a "nontrivial" ring, namely one such that S≠{0}, 0 being the additive identity element. The nearest thing to an identity implying S≠{0} is the nonidentity 0≠1, which requires that the additive and multiplicative identities be distinct.
  2. Axioms involving multiplication, holding for all members of S (or R or K) except 0. In order for an algebraic structure to be a variety, the domain of each operation must be an entire underlying set; there can be no partial operations.
  3. "0 is not the successor of anything," included in nearly all arithmetics.

Most of the classic results of universal algebra do not hold for nonvarieties. For example, neither the free field over any set nor the direct product of integral domains exists. Nevertheless, nonvarieties often retain an undoubted algebraic flavor.

There are whole classes of axiomatic formal systems not included in this section, e.g., logics, topological spaces, and this exclusion is in some sense arbitrary. Many of the nonvarieties below were included because of their intrinsic interest and importance, either by virtue of their foundational nature (Peano arithmetic), ubiquity (the real field), or richness (e.g., fields, normed vector spaces). Also, a great deal of theoretical physics can be recast using the nonvarieties called multilinear algebras.

No operations. Functions or relations may be present:

Arithmetics

If the name of a structure in this section includes the word "arithmetic," the structure features one or both of the binary operations addition and multiplication. If both operations are included, the recursive identity defining multiplication usually links them. Arithmetics necessarily have infinite models.

In the structures below, addition and multiplication, if present, are recursively defined by means of an injective operation called successor, denoted by prefix σ. 0 is the axiomatic identity element for addition, and annihilates multiplication. Both axioms hold for semirings.

Arithmetics above this line are decidable. Those below are incompletable.

  • Peano arithmetic: Robinson arithmetic with an axiom schema of induction. The semiring axioms for N (other than x+0=x and x0=0, included in the recursive definitions of addition and multiplication) are now theorems.

The following arithmetics lack a connection between addition and multiplication. They are the simplest arithmetics capable of expressing all primitive recursive functions.

Lattices that are not varieties

Two sets, Φ and D.

Field-like structures

Two binary operations, addition and multiplication. S is nontrivial, i.e., S≠{0}. S-0 is S with 0 removed.

The following field-like structures are not varieties for reasons in addition to S≠{0}:

Vector spaces that are not varieties

The following composite structures are extensions of vector spaces that are not varieties. Two sets: M is a set of vectors and R is a set of scalars.

Three binary operations.

Structures that build on the notion of vector space:

Multilinear algebras

Four binary operations. Two sets, V and K:

  1. The members of V are multivectors (including vectors), denoted by lower case Latin letters. V is an abelian group under multivector addition, and a monoid under outer product. The outer product goes under various names, and is multilinear in principle but usually bilinear. The outer product defines the multivectors recursively starting from the vectors. Thus the members of V have a "degree" (see graded algebra below). Multivectors may have an inner product as well, denoted uv: V×VK, that is symmetric, linear, and positive definite; see inner product space above.
  2. The properties and notation of K are the same as those of R above, except that K may have -1 as a distinguished member. K is usually the real field, as multilinear algebras are designed to describe physical phenomena without complex numbers.
  3. The scalar multiplication of scalars and multivectors, V×KV, has the same properties as module scalar multiplication.

Structures with topologies or manifolds

These algebraic structures are not varieties, because the underlying set either has a topology or is a manifold, characteristics that are not algebraic in nature. This added structure must be compatible in some sense, however, with the algebraic structure. The case of when the added structure is partial order is discussed above, under varieties.

Topology:

Manifold:

Categories

Let there be two classes:

Let x and y be any two elements of M. Then there exist:

Category: Composition associates (if defined), and x has left and right identity elements, the domain and codomain of x, respectively, so that d(x)x = x = xc(x). Letting φ stand for one of c or d, and γ stand for the other, then φ(γ(x)) = γ(x). If O has but one element, the associated category is a monoid.

Unclassified

Examples

Recurring underlying sets: N=natural numbers; Z=integers; Q=rational numbers; R=real numbers; C=complex numbers.

Arithmetics

Group-like structures

Also see examples of groups, list of small groups, and list of finite simple groups.

Lattices

Ring-like structures

Field-like structures

Lie groups: See table of Lie groups and list of simple Lie groups.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Wolfram, Steven (2002) A New Kind of Science, p. 1171.
  2. ^ Słomczyńska, Katarzyna (2008) "Free equivalential algebras", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 155: 86-96
  3. ^ Wolfram, Steven (2002) A New Kind of Science, p. 803.
  4. ^ Jezek, J., and Ralph McKenzie (2001) "The Variety Generated by Equivalence Algebras," Algebra Universalis 45: 212, Prop. 1.1.
  5. ^ Wolfram, Steven (2002) A New Kind of Science, p. 803.
  6. ^ McCune, William (1993) "Single Axioms for Groups and Abelian Groups with Various Operations," Journal of Automated Reasoning 10:1-13.
  7. ^ Pp. 26-28, 251, of Paul Halmos (1962) Algebraic Logic. Chelsea.
  8. ^ Givant, Steven, 2006, "The calculus of relations as a foundation for mathematics," Journal of Automated Reasoning 37: 277-322.
  9. ^ Raymond Smullyan (1994) Diagonalization and Self-Reference. Oxford Univ. Press: chpt. 18.
  10. ^ Smorynski (1991).
  11. ^ Potter (2004: 90).
  12. ^ Machover, M., 1996. Sets, Logic, and their Limitations. Cambridge Univ. Press: 10.9.
  13. ^ Alfred Tarski, Andrej Mostowski, and Raphael Robinson, 1953. Undecidable Theories. North-Holland: 53.
  14. ^ Birkhoff and MacLane (1979: 369).
  15. ^ Cohn, Paul, 1965. Universal Algebra, chpt. VII.1.
  16. ^ Lewis (1991).

References

A monograph available free online:

External links